-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Induction.v
861 lines (669 loc) · 29.3 KB
/
Induction.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
(** * Induction: Proof by Induction *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Separate Compilation *)
(** Before getting started on this chapter, we need to import
all of our definitions from the previous chapter: *)
From LF Require Export Basics.
(** For this [Require Export] command to work, Coq needs to be
able to find a compiled version of [Basics.v], called [Basics.vo],
in a directory associated with the prefix [LF]. This file is
analogous to the [.class] files compiled from [.java] source files
and the [.o] files compiled from [.c] files.
First create a file named [_CoqProject] containing the following
line (if you obtained the whole volume "Logical Foundations" as a
single archive, a [_CoqProject] should already exist and you can
skip this step):
[-Q . LF]
This maps the current directory ("[.]", which contains [Basics.v],
[Induction.v], etc.) to the prefix (or "logical directory")
"[LF]". PG and CoqIDE read [_CoqProject] automatically, so they
know to where to look for the file [Basics.vo] corresponding to
the library [LF.Basics].
Once [_CoqProject] is thus created, there are various ways to
build [Basics.vo]:
- In Proof General: The compilation can be made to happen
automatically when you submit the [Require] line above to PG,
by setting the emacs variable [coq-compile-before-require] to
[t]. You can also use the menu option "Coq -> Auto
Compilation -> Compile Before Require".
- In CoqIDE: Open [Basics.v]; then, in the "Compile" menu, click
on "Compile Buffer".
- From the command line: Generate a [Makefile] using the
[coq_makefile] utility, that comes installed with Coq (if you
obtained the whole volume as a single archive, a [Makefile]
should already exist and you can skip this step):
[coq_makefile -f _CoqProject *.v -o Makefile]
Note: You should rerun that command whenever you add or remove
Coq files to the directory.
Now you can compile [Basics.v] by running [make] with the
corresponding [.vo] file as a target:
[make Basics.vo]
All files in the directory can be compiled by giving no
arguments:
[make]
Under the hood, [make] uses the Coq compiler, [coqc]. You can
also run [coqc] directly:
[coqc -Q . LF Basics.v]
But [make] also calculates dependencies between source files to
compile them in the right order, so [make] should generally be
prefered over explicit [coqc].
If you have trouble (e.g., if you get complaints about missing
identifiers later in the file), it may be because the "load path"
for Coq is not set up correctly. The [Print LoadPath.] command
may be helpful in sorting out such issues.
In particular, if you see a message like
[Compiled library Foo makes inconsistent assumptions over
library Bar]
check whether you have multiple installations of Coq on your
machine. It may be that commands (like [coqc]) that you execute
in a terminal window are getting a different version of Coq than
commands executed by Proof General or CoqIDE.
- Another common reason is that the library [Bar] was modified and
recompiled without also recompiling [Foo] which depends on it.
Recompile [Foo], or everything if too many files are
affected. (Using the third solution above: [make clean; make].)
One more tip for CoqIDE users: If you see messages like [Error:
Unable to locate library Basics], a likely reason is
inconsistencies between compiling things _within CoqIDE_ vs _using
[coqc] from the command line_. This typically happens when there
are two incompatible versions of [coqc] installed on your
system (one associated with CoqIDE, and one associated with [coqc]
from the terminal). The workaround for this situation is
compiling using CoqIDE only (i.e. choosing "make" from the menu),
and avoiding using [coqc] directly at all. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Proof by Induction *)
(** We can prove that [0] is a neutral element for [+] on the left
using just [reflexivity]. But the proof that it is also a neutral
element on the _right_ ... *)
Theorem plus_n_O_firsttry : forall n:nat,
n = n + 0.
(** ... can't be done in the same simple way. Just applying
[reflexivity] doesn't work, since the [n] in [n + 0] is an arbitrary
unknown number, so the [match] in the definition of [+] can't be
simplified. *)
Proof.
intros n.
simpl. (* Does nothing! *)
Abort.
(** And reasoning by cases using [destruct n] doesn't get us much
further: the branch of the case analysis where we assume [n = 0]
goes through fine, but in the branch where [n = S n'] for some [n'] we
get stuck in exactly the same way. *)
Theorem plus_n_O_secondtry : forall n:nat,
n = n + 0.
Proof.
intros n. destruct n as [| n'] eqn:E.
- (* n = 0 *)
reflexivity. (* so far so good... *)
- (* n = S n' *)
simpl. (* ...but here we are stuck again *)
Abort.
(** We could use [destruct n'] to get one step further, but,
since [n] can be arbitrarily large, we'll never get all the there
if we just go on like this. *)
(** To prove interesting facts about numbers, lists, and other
inductively defined sets, we often need a more powerful reasoning
principle: _induction_.
Recall (from high school, a discrete math course, etc.) the
_principle of induction over natural numbers_: If [P(n)] is some
proposition involving a natural number [n] and we want to show
that [P] holds for all numbers [n], we can reason like this:
- show that [P(O)] holds;
- show that, for any [n'], if [P(n')] holds, then so does
[P(S n')];
- conclude that [P(n)] holds for all [n].
In Coq, the steps are the same: we begin with the goal of proving
[P(n)] for all [n] and break it down (by applying the [induction]
tactic) into two separate subgoals: one where we must show [P(O)]
and another where we must show [P(n') -> P(S n')]. Here's how
this works for the theorem at hand: *)
Theorem plus_n_O : forall n:nat, n = n + 0.
Proof.
intros n. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *) reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl. rewrite <- IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Like [destruct], the [induction] tactic takes an [as...]
clause that specifies the names of the variables to be introduced
in the subgoals. Since there are two subgoals, the [as...] clause
has two parts, separated by [|]. (Strictly speaking, we can omit
the [as...] clause and Coq will choose names for us. In practice,
this is a bad idea, as Coq's automatic choices tend to be
confusing.)
In the first subgoal, [n] is replaced by [0]. No new variables
are introduced (so the first part of the [as...] is empty), and
the goal becomes [0 = 0 + 0], which follows by simplification.
In the second subgoal, [n] is replaced by [S n'], and the
assumption [n' + 0 = n'] is added to the context with the name
[IHn'] (i.e., the Induction Hypothesis for [n']). These two names
are specified in the second part of the [as...] clause. The goal
in this case becomes [S n' = (S n') + 0], which simplifies to
[S n' = S (n' + 0)], which in turn follows from [IHn']. *)
Theorem minus_n_n : forall n,
minus n n = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *)
simpl. reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *)
simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** (The use of the [intros] tactic in these proofs is actually
redundant. When applied to a goal that contains quantified
variables, the [induction] tactic will automatically move them
into the context as needed.) *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (basic_induction)
Prove the following using induction. You might need previously
proven results. *)
Theorem mult_0_r : forall n:nat,
n * 0 = 0.
Proof.
intro n. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *) simpl. reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity.
Qed.
Theorem plus_n_Sm : forall n m : nat,
S (n + m) = n + (S m).
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *) simpl. reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity.
Qed.
Check plus_n_O.
Theorem plus_comm : forall n m : nat,
n + m = m + n.
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *) rewrite -> plus_O_n. rewrite <- plus_n_O. reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. rewrite <- plus_n_Sm. reflexivity.
Qed.
Theorem plus_assoc : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof.
intros n m p. induction n as [|n' IHn'].
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (double_plus)
Consider the following function, which doubles its argument: *)
Fixpoint double (n:nat) :=
match n with
| O => O
| S n' => S (S (double n'))
end.
(** Use induction to prove this simple fact about [double]: *)
Lemma double_plus : forall n, double n = n + n .
Proof.
intro n. induction n as [|n' IHn'].
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. rewrite -> plus_n_Sm. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (evenb_S)
One inconvenient aspect of our definition of [evenb n] is the
recursive call on [n - 2]. This makes proofs about [evenb n]
harder when done by induction on [n], since we may need an
induction hypothesis about [n - 2]. The following lemma gives an
alternative characterization of [evenb (S n)] that works better
with induction: *)
Theorem evenb_S : forall n : nat,
evenb (S n) = negb (evenb n).
Proof.
intro n. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- simpl. reflexivity.
- rewrite -> IHn'. simpl. rewrite -> negb_involutive. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (destruct_induction)
Briefly explain the difference between the tactics [destruct]
and [induction].
(* FILL IN HERE *)
*)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_destruct_induction : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Proofs Within Proofs *)
(** In Coq, as in informal mathematics, large proofs are often
broken into a sequence of theorems, with later proofs referring to
earlier theorems. But sometimes a proof will require some
miscellaneous fact that is too trivial and of too little general
interest to bother giving it its own top-level name. In such
cases, it is convenient to be able to simply state and prove the
needed "sub-theorem" right at the point where it is used. The
[assert] tactic allows us to do this. *)
Theorem mult_0_plus' : forall n m : nat,
(0 + n) * m = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m.
assert (H: 0 + n = n). { reflexivity. }
rewrite -> H.
reflexivity. Qed.
(** The [assert] tactic introduces two sub-goals. The first is
the assertion itself; by prefixing it with [H:] we name the
assertion [H]. (We can also name the assertion with [as] just as
we did above with [destruct] and [induction], i.e., [assert (0 + n
= n) as H].) Note that we surround the proof of this assertion
with curly braces [{ ... }], both for readability and so that,
when using Coq interactively, we can see more easily when we have
finished this sub-proof. The second goal is the same as the one
at the point where we invoke [assert] except that, in the context,
we now have the assumption [H] that [0 + n = n]. That is,
[assert] generates one subgoal where we must prove the asserted
fact and a second subgoal where we can use the asserted fact to
make progress on whatever we were trying to prove in the first
place. *)
(** For example, suppose we want to prove that [(n + m) + (p + q)
= (m + n) + (p + q)]. The only difference between the two sides of
the [=] is that the arguments [m] and [n] to the first inner [+]
are swapped, so it seems we should be able to use the
commutativity of addition ([plus_comm]) to rewrite one into the
other. However, the [rewrite] tactic is not very smart about
_where_ it applies the rewrite. There are three uses of [+] here,
and it turns out that doing [rewrite -> plus_comm] will affect
only the _outer_ one... *)
Theorem plus_rearrange_firsttry : forall n m p q : nat,
(n + m) + (p + q) = (m + n) + (p + q).
Proof.
intros n m p q.
(* We just need to swap (n + m) for (m + n)... seems
like plus_comm should do the trick! *)
rewrite -> plus_comm.
(* Doesn't work... Coq rewrites the wrong plus! :-( *)
Abort.
(** To use [plus_comm] at the point where we need it, we can introduce
a local lemma stating that [n + m = m + n] (for the _particular_ [m]
and [n] that we are talking about here), prove this lemma using
[plus_comm], and then use it to do the desired rewrite. *)
Theorem plus_rearrange : forall n m p q : nat,
(n + m) + (p + q) = (m + n) + (p + q).
Proof.
intros n m p q.
assert (H: n + m = m + n).
{ rewrite -> plus_comm. reflexivity. }
rewrite -> H. reflexivity. Qed.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Formal vs. Informal Proof *)
(** "_Informal proofs are algorithms; formal proofs are code_." *)
(** What constitutes a successful proof of a mathematical claim?
The question has challenged philosophers for millennia, but a
rough and ready definition could be this: A proof of a
mathematical proposition [P] is a written (or spoken) text that
instills in the reader or hearer the certainty that [P] is true --
an unassailable argument for the truth of [P]. That is, a proof
is an act of communication.
Acts of communication may involve different sorts of readers. On
one hand, the "reader" can be a program like Coq, in which case
the "belief" that is instilled is that [P] can be mechanically
derived from a certain set of formal logical rules, and the proof
is a recipe that guides the program in checking this fact. Such
recipes are _formal_ proofs.
Alternatively, the reader can be a human being, in which case the
proof will be written in English or some other natural language,
and will thus necessarily be _informal_. Here, the criteria for
success are less clearly specified. A "valid" proof is one that
makes the reader believe [P]. But the same proof may be read by
many different readers, some of whom may be convinced by a
particular way of phrasing the argument, while others may not be.
Some readers may be particularly pedantic, inexperienced, or just
plain thick-headed; the only way to convince them will be to make
the argument in painstaking detail. But other readers, more
familiar in the area, may find all this detail so overwhelming
that they lose the overall thread; all they want is to be told the
main ideas, since it is easier for them to fill in the details for
themselves than to wade through a written presentation of them.
Ultimately, there is no universal standard, because there is no
single way of writing an informal proof that is guaranteed to
convince every conceivable reader.
In practice, however, mathematicians have developed a rich set of
conventions and idioms for writing about complex mathematical
objects that -- at least within a certain community -- make
communication fairly reliable. The conventions of this stylized
form of communication give a fairly clear standard for judging
proofs good or bad.
Because we are using Coq in this course, we will be working
heavily with formal proofs. But this doesn't mean we can
completely forget about informal ones! Formal proofs are useful
in many ways, but they are _not_ very efficient ways of
communicating ideas between human beings. *)
(** For example, here is a proof that addition is associative: *)
Theorem plus_assoc' : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof. intros n m p. induction n as [| n' IHn']. reflexivity.
simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Coq is perfectly happy with this. For a human, however, it
is difficult to make much sense of it. We can use comments and
bullets to show the structure a little more clearly... *)
Theorem plus_assoc'' : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
Proof.
intros n m p. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- (* n = 0 *)
reflexivity.
- (* n = S n' *)
simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** ... and if you're used to Coq you may be able to step
through the tactics one after the other in your mind and imagine
the state of the context and goal stack at each point, but if the
proof were even a little bit more complicated this would be next
to impossible.
A (pedantic) mathematician might write the proof something like
this: *)
(** - _Theorem_: For any [n], [m] and [p],
n + (m + p) = (n + m) + p.
_Proof_: By induction on [n].
- First, suppose [n = 0]. We must show that
0 + (m + p) = (0 + m) + p.
This follows directly from the definition of [+].
- Next, suppose [n = S n'], where
n' + (m + p) = (n' + m) + p.
We must now show that
(S n') + (m + p) = ((S n') + m) + p.
By the definition of [+], this follows from
S (n' + (m + p)) = S ((n' + m) + p),
which is immediate from the induction hypothesis. _Qed_. *)
(** The overall form of the proof is basically similar, and of
course this is no accident: Coq has been designed so that its
[induction] tactic generates the same sub-goals, in the same
order, as the bullet points that a mathematician would write. But
there are significant differences of detail: the formal proof is
much more explicit in some ways (e.g., the use of [reflexivity])
but much less explicit in others (in particular, the "proof state"
at any given point in the Coq proof is completely implicit,
whereas the informal proof reminds the reader several times where
things stand). *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, advanced, especially useful (plus_comm_informal)
Translate your solution for [plus_comm] into an informal proof:
Theorem: Addition is commutative.forall m, n : nat , m + n = n + m
By induction on [n].
- First [ n = 0 ]. We must show
m + 0 = 0 + m
By the defintion of [+] and rules plus_n_0 we get
m = 0 + m
By the defintion of [+] and rules plus_0_n we get
m = m
- Next, suppose [n = S n'], where
m + n' = n' + m
We must now show that
m + S n' = S n' + m
By plus_n_Sm we get
S(m + n') = S n' + m
By the induction hypothesis
S(n' + m) = S n' + m.
By plus_1_l we get
1 + (n' + m) = S n' + m
By plus_1_l we get
1 + (n' + m) = (1 + n') + m
By plus_assoc we get
1 + (n' + m) = 1 + (n' + m)
and by the definition of [+] the equation holds true. QED
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)
*)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_plus_comm_informal : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (eqb_refl_informal)
Write an informal proof of the following theorem, using the
informal proof of [plus_assoc] as a model. Don't just
paraphrase the Coq tactics into English!
Theorem: [true = n =? n] for any [n].
Proof:
Induction on [n].
- First let [n = 0]. We now have to show
true = 0 =? 0
which holds.
- Next let [n = S n'] and
true = n' =? n'
We now need to show
true = S n' =? S n'
by plus_1_l we get
true = 1 + n' =? 1 + n'
by IH we know that [n' = n'] and by [+] we can deduce
true = 1 + n' =? 1 + n'
*)
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * More Exercises *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, especially useful (mult_comm)
Use [assert] to help prove [plus_swap]. You don't need to
use induction yet. *)
Theorem plus_swap : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = m + (n + p).
Proof.
intros n m p. assert (H: n + m = m + n).
{ rewrite -> plus_comm. reflexivity. }
rewrite -> plus_assoc. rewrite -> plus_assoc. rewrite -> H. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Now prove commutativity of multiplication. You will probably
want to define and prove a "helper" theorem to be used
in the proof of this one. Hint: what is [n * (1 + k)]? *)
(*
Theorem mult_dist: forall n m : nat,
m * S n = m + n * m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
* simpl. rewrite -> mult_n_1. rewrite <- plus_n_O. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite <- IHn'. rewrite <- plus_1_l. rewrite -> mult *)
Theorem mult_comm : forall m n : nat,
m * n = n * m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
* simpl. rewrite -> mult_0_r. reflexivity.
* simpl. assert (H: m * (1 + n') = m + n' * m).
{ simpl. rewrite <- plus_comm. rewrite <- mult_n_Sm.
rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. }
rewrite <- plus_1_l. rewrite -> H. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (more_exercises)
Take a piece of paper. For each of the following theorems, first
_think_ about whether (a) it can be proved using only
simplification and rewriting, (b) it also requires case
analysis ([destruct]), or (c) it also requires induction. Write
down your prediction. Then fill in the proof. (There is no need
to turn in your piece of paper; this is just to encourage you to
reflect before you hack!) *)
Check leb.
Theorem leb_refl : forall n:nat,
true = (n <=? n).
Proof.
intro n. induction n as [| n' IHn'].
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem zero_nbeq_S : forall n:nat,
0 =? (S n) = false.
Proof.
intro n. destruct n as [| n'] eqn:E.
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem andb_false_r : forall b : bool,
andb b false = false.
Proof.
intro b. destruct b.
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem plus_ble_compat_l : forall n m p : nat,
n <=? m = true -> (p + n) <=? (p + m) = true.
Proof.
intros n m p. intro H. induction p as [| p' IHp'].
* simpl. rewrite -> H. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite -> IHp'. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem S_nbeq_0 : forall n:nat,
(S n) =? 0 = false.
Proof.
intro n. destruct n as [| n' ].
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_1_l : forall n:nat, 1 * n = n.
Proof.
intro n. simpl. rewrite -> plus_n_O. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem all3_spec : forall b c : bool,
orb
(andb b c)
(orb (negb b)
(negb c))
= true.
Proof.
intros b c. destruct b.
* simpl. destruct c.
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_plus_distr_r : forall n m p : nat,
(n + m) * p = (n * p) + (m * p).
Proof.
intros n m p. induction n as [| n' IHn' ].
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. rewrite -> plus_assoc. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem mult_assoc : forall n m p : nat,
n * (m * p) = (n * m) * p.
Proof.
intros n m p. induction n as [| n' IHn' ].
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. rewrite -> mult_plus_distr_r. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (eqb_refl) *)
Theorem eqb_refl : forall n : nat,
true = (n =? n).
Proof.
intro n. induction n as [| n' IHn' ].
* simpl. reflexivity.
* simpl. rewrite -> IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (plus_swap')
The [replace] tactic allows you to specify a particular subterm to
rewrite and what you want it rewritten to: [replace (t) with (u)]
replaces (all copies of) expression [t] in the goal by expression
[u], and generates [t = u] as an additional subgoal. This is often
useful when a plain [rewrite] acts on the wrong part of the goal.
Use the [replace] tactic to do a proof of [plus_swap'], just like
[plus_swap] but without needing [assert]. *)
Theorem plus_swap' : forall n m p : nat,
n + (m + p) = m + (n + p).
Proof.
intros n m p. rewrite -> plus_assoc. rewrite -> plus_assoc.
replace (n + m) with (m + n).
* reflexivity.
* rewrite -> plus_comm. reflexivity. Qed.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, especially useful (binary_commute)
Recall the [incr] and [bin_to_nat] functions that you
wrote for the [binary] exercise in the [Basics] chapter. Prove
that the following diagram commutes:
incr
bin ----------------------> bin
| |
bin_to_nat | | bin_to_nat
| |
v v
nat ----------------------> nat
S
That is, incrementing a binary number and then converting it to
a (unary) natural number yields the same result as first converting
it to a natural number and then incrementing.
Name your theorem [bin_to_nat_pres_incr] ("pres" for "preserves").
Before you start working on this exercise, copy the definitions of
[incr] and [bin_to_nat] from your solution to the [binary]
exercise here so that this file can be graded on its own. If you
want to change your original definitions to make the property
easier to prove, feel free to do so! *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
Fixpoint incr(m:bin) : bin :=
match m with
| Z => B1 Z
| B0 n => B1 n
| B1 n => B0 (incr n)
end.
Fixpoint bin_to_nat (m:bin) : nat :=
match m with
| Z => 0
| B0 n => mult 2 (bin_to_nat n)
| B1 n => S (mult 2 (bin_to_nat n))
end.
Theorem bin_to_nat_pres_incr: forall (n: bin),
bin_to_nat (incr n) = S (bin_to_nat n).
Proof.
induction n as [| n IHn | n IHn].
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite IHn. simpl. rewrite <- plus_n_O. rewrite <- plus_n_Sm. reflexivity.
Qed.
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_binary_commute : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, advanced (binary_inverse)
This is a further continuation of the previous exercises about
binary numbers. You may find you need to go back and change your
earlier definitions to get things to work here.
(a) First, write a function to convert natural numbers to binary
numbers.
*)
Fixpoint nat_to_bin (n:nat) : bin :=
match n with
| 0 => Z
| S n' => incr (nat_to_bin n')
end.
(** Prove that, if we start with any [nat], convert it to binary, and
convert it back, we get the same [nat] we started with. (Hint: If
your definition of [nat_to_bin] involved any extra functions, you
may need to prove a subsidiary lemma showing how such functions
relate to [nat_to_bin].) *)
Theorem nat_bin_nat : forall n, bin_to_nat (nat_to_bin n) = n.
Proof.
induction n as [| n' IHn'].
- reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite bin_to_nat_pres_incr. rewrite IHn'. reflexivity. Qed.
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_binary_inverse_a : option (nat*string) := None.
(** (b) One might naturally expect that we should also prove the
opposite direction -- that starting with a binary number,
converting to a natural, and then back to binary should yield
the same number we started with. However, this is not the
case! Explain (in a comment) what the problem is. *)
(*
There are multiple binary representations for 0, 0, 00, 00000,
000000, etc. so starting from 0000 we get 0 which though different
representations they denote the same value.
*)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_binary_inverse_b : option (nat*string) := None.
(** (c) Define a normalization function -- i.e., a function
[normalize] going directly from [bin] to [bin] (i.e., _not_ by
converting to [nat] and back) such that, for any binary number
[b], converting [b] to a natural and then back to binary yields
[(normalize b)]. Prove it. (Warning: This part is a bit
tricky -- you may end up defining several auxiliary lemmas.
One good way to find out what you need is to start by trying
to prove the main statement, see where you get stuck, and see
if you can find a lemma -- perhaps requiring its own inductive
proof -- that will allow the main proof to make progress.) Don't
define this using [nat_to_bin] and [bin_to_nat]! *)
Fixpoint is_zero (n: bin) : bool :=
match n with
| Z => true
| B0 n' => is_zero n'
| B1 n' => false
end.
Fixpoint normalize (n: bin) : bin :=
match n with
| Z => Z
| B0 n' => if (is_zero n') then Z else B0 (normalize n')
| B1 n' => B1 (normalize n')
end.
Theorem nat_plut_to_bin_double: forall n,
nat_to_bin(n + n) = normalize (B0 (nat_to_bin n)).
Proof.
(* intro n. induction n as [| n' IHn']. *)
(* - simpl. reflexivity. *)
(* - simpl. *)
Admitted.
Theorem nat_2_bin_2_nat: forall n,
nat_to_bin (bin_to_nat n) = normalize n.
Proof.
(* induction n as [| b0 IHb0| b1 IHb1]. *)
(* - simpl. reflexivity. *)
(* - simpl. rewrite <- plus_n_O. *)
Admitted.
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_binary_inverse_c : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(* 2020-10-01 08:07 *)